Wednesday, October 1, 2014

Chapter Two: Heavy Traffic on the Wredebahn: The ‘New Quest’ Renewed?


[This is an ongoing project that is analyzing N.T. Wright’s 5 volume series, Christian Origins and the Question of God. This series is widely read and bridges the gap between the academic and devotional world. It is therefore worthy to be carefully analyzed so that all readers can understand his key points while at the same time gaining a critical eye to some of his rather bold claims. This series of posts are concerning volume 2 – Jesus and the Victory of God.]

This chapter and the one following both are wide ranging scholarly overviews of what Wright sees as the two sides of historical Jesus scholarship. He argues that the scholarship on Jesus up to 1996 when the book was published can be categorized (at least initially) in two groups – that which develops from William Wrede and that which develops from Albert Schweitzer. There is some reason to challenge this division, but as far as divisions are helpful, this is a heuristic category that might be useful as a way of managing the complexities of the vast material covered under “historical Jesus studies.” This chapter covers what he considers the legacy of William Wrede which is often called the “New Quest” of the historical Jesus. Wright challenges this wing of scholarship and in so doing does not give this wing its fair due – his criticism of the scholarship colors it as “incorrect” rather than a true survey which would give the reader context.

First, Wright properly admits that he feels that this wing of scholarship is more incorrect than its inverse. He hardly completely agrees with the “Third Quest” (to be discussed in the next chapter), but does agree with it far more than he agrees with this “New Quest.” Wright explains:
I still believe that the future of a serious Jesus research lies with what I have called the ‘Third Quest,’ within a broadly post-Schweitzerian frame of reference, and to this we must presently turn.[1]
Wright here admits that the “New Quest” is not something he particularly values – he finds that in the “Third Quest.” While it is no problem for a scholar to make clear which side he values, his supposed goal in the chapter is to give readers a sense of scholarship on the subject. Given that, it would be prudent to attempt to avoid such biases.

Wright’s biases are shown in his justification of discussing the “New Quest” at all. Instead, he argues that it should be discussed precisely for its not being followed. He argues that many figures in this “New Quest” do not actually hold the views of the New Quest and as a result, are of value:
But these artificial distinctions do not do justice to the manysidedness of contemporary scholarship. It is increasingly clear that there are cross-over points between different schools, and that those who immerse themselves most thoroughly in the material, especially the historical sources, are mostly likely to move to and fro across what had seemed a firm Green Line into what some of their colleagues may still regard as no-go areas.[2]
While Wright is certainly correct that no firm distinctions ever hold up given scrutiny, what is more concerning is why he inserts this particular passage. He seems to suggest this, not so that people can understand the complexity of the issue, but far more because this is where the “New Quest” can have any value at all. He seems to suggest this in regard to validity rather than understanding. That alone illustrates the problem.

He therefore argues that the New Quest’s value can only be understood if the categories fall apart and the failures of the New Quest is revealed. Wright explains, “If the categories crumble in the next decade or so, that will be an excellent thing for the discipline…But that will only happen if the residual weaknesses in the New Quest are seriously addressed.”[3] Here Wright argues that the only productive way that the New Quest can be used is if the “categories crumble.” While I would generally agree that his categories aren’t that helpful, I am not sure I would agree that the way for the categories to crumble are necessarily for everyone to agree with Wright. He seems to feel that the “weaknesses” of the New Quest need to be abandoned which translate into Wright’s own conclusions.

Wright argues that the first thing the “New Quest” needs to do is to be card carrying about their premises. He feels that all work on the historical Jesus is governed by its premises. After this, these unprovable premises then govern the scarce data that we have:
First, there is the continued Bultmannian reliance on the sayings of Jesus as the primary material…This reliance on sayings leads, second, to a spurious idea that history can be done by assessing these sayings through ‘criteria’ of various sorts…Both, as we saw, are extremely difficult to assess, despite the confident feel of Crossan’s inventory, and are open to the charge that they simply reflect decisions reached on quite other grounds. All the current New Questers point, despite themselves, to a correct solution: the scholar must work with a large hypothesis, and must appeal, ultimately, to the large picture of how everything fits together as justification for smaller-scale decisions.[4]
Here, at least on a logical level, Wright is certainly accurate. That one’s epistemology (what he is here calling a “large hypothesis”) governs one’s conclusions is not surprising. It is, after all, one of the fundamental tenets of philosophy. The problem is that he seems to suggest that the New Quest movement has not done this. While certain figures certainly have not, better scholars have. Crossan’s work – however one feels about it – should not be criticized for its lack of rigor or its clarity of its epistemology.

The real problem Wright has with the New Quest is not that the premises aren’t defined. His real problem is that he doesn’t like their premises. He feels that the presentation does not take seriously enough Jesus’ Jewish origins and that it creates a Hellenistic figure in a world where a better explanation would have him in a fully Jewish contour:
The renewed New Quest works, third, with an overall picture of Christian origins that ought now to be abandoned. It is the Bultmannian picture, with variations: a deJudaized Jesus preaching a demythologized, ‘vertical’ eschatology; a crucifixion with no early theological interpretation; a ‘resurrection’ consisting of the coming to faith, some time later, of a particular group of Christians; an early sapiential/gnostic group, retelling the master’s aphorisms but uninterested in his life story; a Paul who invented a Hellenistic Christ-cult; a synoptic tradition in which rolling aphorisms, as they slowed down, gathered the moss of narrative structure about themselves, and gradually congealed into gospels in which the initial force of Jesus’ challenge was muted or lost altogether within a fictitious pseudo-historical framework.[5]
Here Wright comes clean – his problem is not really in method, it is in conclusion. He feels that this picture of Jesus in its epistemological model is flawed. Wright instead feels that whatever conclusion about Jesus needs to be a Jewish Jesus that works in a Jewish Christian framework. He explains:
I have already argued in some detail that when we find solid historical ground under our feet in the first century of Christianity, we find ourselves still in a very Jewish world, even if transplanted to Rome, Smyrna, or Thessalonica. There is one true god who challenges all the other gods, and those who worship this one true god must offer allegiance to no others.[6]
Wright correctly wants Jesus to fit a Jewish worldview and that in that Jewish worldview Christians remained – even to the extent that it included gentiles who were unfamiliar with Jewish tradition.

Wright’s argument that the premise should be challenged for its “Jewishness” should be reconsidered. There certainly is good reason to question how “Hellenistic” Judaism was in Palestine as the work of Mark Chancey has shown.[7] However, there is equal reason to challenge how non-Hellenic it was as expressed by Martin Hengel.[8] There was far less a “different type” of Judaism in Palestine than in other areas of the Roman Empire. The old distinction between the Hellenistic diaspora and the traditional Israel is less sure. There seems to be far more intermingling of ideas. It was certainly possible that one could hold Stoic theology while at the same time holding to Jewish tradition. After all, a good argument can be made that Paul himself had an idea very much like this as expressed by Stanley Stowers.[9]

All of this does not suggest that Wright was wrong with his conclusion – I myself would agree more with Schweitzer than Wrede - but it does show the challenge of being able to create a reasonable survey without inherently judging it. I am not arguing that Wright should have created such a unbiased survey – such a thing is difficult if not impossible – but it then raises the question why he bothered to discuss this at all. If his goal were simply to dismiss counter-opinions, would it not have been easier to do this after presenting his clear thesis? In all, more work could have been done to clarify key questions.




[1] JVG, 78.
[2] Ibid., 78.
[3] Ibid., 79.
[4] Ibid.
[5] Ibid., 79-80.
[6] Ibid., 71.
[7] Mark Chancey Greco-Roman Culture and the Galilee of Jesus (Cambridge: CUP, 2005).
[8] Martin Hengel Judaism and Hellenism: Studies in their encounter in Palestine during the early Hellenistic Period 2 vols. (Philadelphia, Fortress Press, 1974).
[9] Stanley Kent Stowers Rereading Romans: Justice, Jews, and Gentiles (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994).

No comments:

Post a Comment