Tuesday, June 17, 2014

Chapter 2: “Knowledge: Problems and Varieties”


[This is an ongoing project that will analyze N.T. Wright’s 5 volume series Christian Origins and the Question of God. This series is widely read and bridges the gap between the academic and devotional world. It is therefore worthy to be carefully analyzed so that all readers can understand his key points while at the same time gaining a critical eye to some of his rather bold claims. This series of posts are concerning volume 1 – The New Testament and the People of God.]

Chapter 2: “Knowledge: Problems and Varieties”

N.T. Wright, in his second chapter of his magnum opus begins to set out a very important theoretical base which will govern the following 5 volumes (and at least one more is forthcoming). It is necessary, then, for us as readers to carefully analyze his approach to historiography. Wright does a good job of having the presence of mind to set out his governing theory that organizes the remainder of his work. Wright is to be lauded for his attempt to take seriously the challenge of modern epistemology to move beyond the shackles of fundamentalism. However, while his intentions are quite good, his application is weak – he attempts to show that one simultaneously interprets all data while at the same time still making positive claims about an object. He presents this well in theory, but his application by means of the concept of “story” fail to hold up to his original theory.

First, Wright is correct that “historiography” is simply one element of a much larger debate on epistemology – how well we can “know” something. Wright explains well that the differences of opinion among scholars are far less due to application of exegetical theory as much as the acceptance of the larger governing theory in the first place.[1] For example, for Lutheran readers who accept the hermeneutic of Law and Gospel, there are relatively few major differences of opinion based upon exegetical reading. However, as soon as one introduces a non-Lutheran reader who does not accept that hermeneutic, no agreement can be found at any level.

To explain this, Wright moves in the parlance of “worldviews.” This common term is his way of suggesting which of the epistemological frameworks one accepts. This, he argues, is the determinative reason there are clear distinctions and disagreements among scholars on readings of the New Testament. At this point, it is not at all surprising what he says and he should be praised for his insights.

Where Wright presents his particular argument, however, is that worldviews are best expressed through his concept of “story.” He argues that story is the thing that creates a worldview:
The basic argument I shall advance in this Part of the book is that the problem of knowledge itself, and the three branches of it that form our particular concern, can all be clarified by seeing them in the light of a detailed analysis of the worldviews which form the grid through which humans, both individually and in social groupings, perceive all of reality. In particular, one of the key features of all worldview is the element of story. This is of vital importance not least in relation to the New Testament and early Christianity, but this is in fact a symptom of a universal phenomenon. “Story,” I shall argue, can help us in the first instance to articulate a critical-realist epistemology, and can then be put to wider uses in the study of literature, history, and theology.[2]
He attempts to focus completely on the aspect of “story” as he believes it is the most productive element of worldview and is the basis upon which one can find knowledge about things.

Wright then tries to make the key argument that “story” is valuable because it moves beyond the myth of “objective” knowledge. Instead, he argues that people can never “know” something in that sense – all things are interpreted at least at some level. He argues that people will not “know” things from data that they then build into a narrative, but rather that they have a preexisting narrative that they then use to interpret a story:
Instead of working as it were upwards from empirical data, in however chastened and hence cautious a fashion, knowledge takes place, within this model, when people find things that fit with the particular story or (more likely) stories to which they are accustomed to give allegiance.[3]
His argument, then, is the idea that one values a particular “story” – or more academically mythos – wherein new data will either fit or not fit. Based upon the coherence of the new data with the old leads one to accept or deny this as something “known.”

Wright further explains that given this framework there is a process wherein one can truly know something. He argues that when this knowledge is processed through what he calls “critical realism,” then it is possible to make positive statements concerning “reality.”
Over against both these positions, I propose a form of critical realism. This is a way of describing the process of ‘knowing’ that acknowledges the reality of the thing known, as something other than the knower (hence ‘realism’), while also fully acknowledging that the only access we have to this reality lies along the spiraling path of appropriate dialogue or conversation between the knower and the thing known (hence ‘critical’). This path leads to critical reflection on the products of our enquiry into ‘reality,’ so that our assertions about ‘reality’ acknowledge their own provisionality. Knowledge, in other words, although in principle concerning realities independent of the knower, is never itself independent of the knower.[4]
He essentially argues that so long as we recognize that we interpret data, we should be able to still value the reality of the object.

This argument is a very paired down presentation of what Charles Sanders Peirce presented in his semeiotic triad. Peirce, studying logical semiotics (signs), argued that a sign can relate to the object only via the interpreter. Pierce argues that there any interpreter of an object (the thing that is actually there), actually dialogues with 2 objects – the object and the representation of that object in the interpreter’s mind. Pierce’s views are therefore called a “triad” in that the interpreter sees and interprets both the actual object and the way that object is represented. Further, the way the object is represented should have a natural relationship with the actual object – therefore, all three elements of the triad are in relationship with each other. The value in Peirce’s logical semeiotics is that it recognizes the human interpreter as one who changes the real object and still allows the real object to exist and be part of the discussion.[5]

Wright’s argument for a Peircean semeiotic – if he is thinking in that complex a manner (he never mentions Peirce in his discussion though his argument seems based upon it) – is a valuable theory. It can be criticized in a variety of ways, but it is a good theory that deserves some attention as it is applied to the New Testament. If Wright were to use this theory and apply it carefully for the first century, his book would be a fascinating triumph. The problem is that he is not able to accomplish this task when he tries to apply this theory to the concept of “story.”

When Wright discusses “story,” he unwittingly abandons Peirce’s triads and moves far closer to a Structuralist idea that gives far less practical place for individuals. First, Wright argues that “stories” are essentially the worldview of individuals: “Stories thus provide a vital framework for experiencing the world. They also provide a means by which views of the world may be challenged.”[6] He considers “stories” – the framework for how we understand the world – as the key interpretant for all experience.

When he applies this process, though, he suggests how it is a story is supported/supplanted, organized by processing new data:
When we examine how stories work in relation to other stories, we find that human beings tell stories because this is how we perceive, and indeed relate to, the world. What we see close up, in a multitude of little incidents whether isolated of (more likely) interrelated, we make sense of drawing on storyforms already more or less known to us and placing the information within them. A story, with its pattern of problem and conflict, of aborted attempts at resolution, and final result, whether sad or glad, is, if we may infer from the common practice of the world, universally perceived as the best way of talking about the way the world actually is. Good stories assume that the world is a place of conflict and resolution, whether comic or tragic. They select and arrange material accordingly. And, as we suggested before, stories can embody or reinforce, or perhaps modify, the worldviews to which they relate.[7]
Here Wright applies his theory to the way people function. He argues that stories are the thing that we already know and the way we manage information by placing new pieces of information into preexisting stories.

This idea, while having some merit, moves away from Peirce’s good model into a more questionable model that is more familiar to us in the figure of Ferdinand de Saussure. Saussure is a semeiotician and is in the same “field” as Pierce. However, Saussure spoke rather differently than Pierce did. He does not speak of any triads. Instead he focuses on a general system which a person knows (which he calls a “langue”). This is the “way of speaking” that governs how we think of things. He argues that this langue was present before we were born and persists outside of ourselves. He further argues that this whole system becomes “real” in that from the langue we can accept and express “parole” – essentially words. He argues that when we see an object, we give it a “parole” so that it fits within our “langue” – essentially, that we form reality to fit our system.[8] This seems to be precisely what Wright suggests a “story” does for a person – it allows the person to place a new piece of information – an “object” – into a system (langue/story) by labeling it in ways that correspond (parole).

The problem with using Saussure when one originally argued that one agreed with Peirce is that Saussure did not take seriously the third element that made Peirce’s model a triad. Peirce was insistent that the way one interpreted the actual object created a new object. In that sense, most all knowledge was not based upon the actual object and how it was signified – rather, most knowledge is based upon the representamen – the way the interpreter has created this “second object.” To deny this is to deny that the individual has much of a role at all.

Therefore, Wright begins laudably – he wants to address the challenge of individual subjectivity while at the same time not falling into the negative trap of logical positivism. He further presents a reasonable (if somewhat controversial) theory to do this by means of Peirce. However, his analysis of “story” – while it might be quite practical and useful – denies the very nuance he wanted to achieve with Peirce. Instead, he essentially has limited the individual to merely be a cog in a much larger machine. This machine is societal and it makes the whole system far less messy and less complex. The problem will be seen is if he has simplified this too much. At best, he has begun a chapter with a goal and then counteracted that same goal.


[1] Wright, NTPG, 31.
[2] Ibid., 32.
[3] Ibid., 37.
[4] Ibid., 35.
[5] For a brief and relatively clear presentation of Peirce’s semeiotics, see Crystal L. Downing, The Changing Signs of Truth: A Christian Introduction to the Semeiotics of Communication (Downers Grove, IL: Intervarsity Press Academic, 2012), 198-220.
[6] Wright, NTPG, 39.
[7] Ibid., 40.
[8] See Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics trans. Wade Baskin (New York: McGraw Hill, 1959).

No comments:

Post a Comment