Wednesday, December 3, 2014

Chapter Two: Shadows, Souls and Where They Go: Life Beyond Death in Ancient Paganism



 [This is an ongoing project that is analyzing N.T. Wright’s 5 volume series, Christian Origins and the Question of God. This series is widely read and bridges the gap between the academic and devotional world. It is therefore worthy to be carefully analyzed so that all readers can understand his key points while at the same time gaining a critical eye to some of his rather bold claims. This series of posts are concerning volume 3 – The Resurrection of the Son of God.]

N.T. Weight’s emphasis in this chapter is laudable. He is primarily interested in how the message of the resurrection would have been heard to a Gentile audience (he will discuss how this same message would have sounded to a Jewish audience in the following two chapters). Wright focuses on the worldview of most members of Greco-Roman society. He does a good job presenting the worldview, but less of a good job showing the possibilities within the world by focusing so exclusively on the concept of resurrection and by not discussing minority religion such as Greek magic or the mystery cults.

First, Wright emphasizes that on the level of the worldview, most people could not have imagined a conversation about any type of “resurrection” in any way that would have made sense to them:
This basic tenet of human existence and experience is accepted as axiomatic throughout the ancient world; once people have gone by the road of death, they do not return. When the ancient classical world spoke of (and denied) resurrection, there should be no controversy about what the word and its cognates referred to: it was a coming back again into something like the same sort of life that humans presently experience.[1]
He argues that any idea of “resurrection” would not be expected because such an idea would be a reanimation of one’s bodies – a view held by very few. While Wright is correct that the focus of Greek and Roman religion is on the present world – and frankly very little speculation about any type of “life after death” – his focus being so narrowly on resurrection causes problems.

First, it is necessary to show where it is that Wright succeeded. He correctly points out that the worldview generally had little interest in life after death. He argues any idea of life after dearth would be something that was not particularly hoped for:
We can, then, answer the worldview questions in relation to the dead. Who were the dead thought to be, in the ancient pagan world? They were beings that had once been the embodied human beings, but were now souls, shades or eidola. Where were they? Most likely in Hades; possibly in the Isles of the Blessed, or Tartarus; just conceivably, reincarnated into a different body altogether. They might occasionally appear to living mortals; they might still be located somewhere in the vicinity of their tombs; but they were basically in a different world. What was wrong? Nothing, for a good Platonist, or a Stoic like Epictetus; the soul was well rid of its body – a sentiment echoed by many non-philosophers in a world without modern medicine, and often without much justice. Almost everything, for most people: some kind of life might continue after death, but it was unlikely to be as rich and satisfying as the present could be, at least in theory.[2]
This is certainly accurate. Most people did not focus on the coming life after death, rather, they focused upon life right now. Roman religion had almost no interest in any kind of future life, instead religious devotion was centered upon a do ut des relationship that addressed current needs (as well as having nearly no interest in ethics).

He illustrates this by showing that life after death in Homer is something that is not what a Western reader would expect. Any type of future existence is not “bodily” in the sense that Christians would later make so popular. Instead, the type of existence was shadowy and elusive:
Who then are the dead, for Homer and the subsequent centuries that read him devoutly? They are shades (skiai), ghosts (psychai), phantoms (eidola). They are in no way full human beings, though they may look like them; the appearance is deceptive, since one cannot grasp them physically. The Latin word Manes conjures up the same sort of world, with similar variations. Where are they? They are in Hades, under the eponymous rule of the underworld’s god and his dread wife. What’s wrong? They are sorry both to be where they are and at much that happened in their previous human existence. They are sad at their present subhuman state. In some cases they are tormented, as punishment for particularly heinous crimes (though we are not told, interesting, the crimes of Tantalus and Sisyphus). There may be some who have a shadowy alter ego in a better place; we shall come to Hercules presently. But for most of them, including those who have been great and goo din their former life, Hades holds no comforts, no prospects, but only a profound sense of loss.[3]
Here Wright is correct – at the level of Homer, there really is very little as far as a Christian life after death. There certainly were not otherworldly expectations of wages of life based upon any kind of merit.

Wright then explains that in philosophy, there was a development of a kind of future life that would be valued. Here, he argues that Plato broke new ground by dividing the soul and the body and having the soul exist in the world of the forms as a kind of happy future:
How will we ever get people to be good citizens, he asks, to serve in the army, to do their duty to their friends, if their view of the future life is conditioned by epic pictures of gibbering ghosts in a gloomy underworld? Instead, the young must be taught the true philosophical view: death is not something to regret, but something to be welcomed. It is the moment when, and means by which, the immortal soul is set free from the prison-house of the physical body…Here is the central difference between Plato and Homer. Instead of the “self” being the physical body, lying dead on the ground, while the “soul” flies away to what is at best a half-life, now the “self,” the true person, is precisely the soul, while it is the corpse that is the ghost.[4]
Wright argues that Plato found a way for some type of afterlife to be of value. In fact, it was of utmost value in the world of the forms when a human could finally stand at rest rather than being tossed to and fro in the vicissitudes of the present world rife with changes.

Wright though, narrowly focusing, argues that Christianity was fundamentally different because this idea of a soul was not “bodily” in the same sense Christians would expect and therefore was not analogous to “resurrection.” He argues that this goal of life is fundamentally different in that it is not bodily in the sense that Christians would expect. However, this is too narrow. There certainly is an expectation of a life after death – just because they did not focus on the issue of resurrection does not make this so foreign that it cannot be fathomed. What seems to be at issue is the nature of the human after death. Rather than being souls (which, in themselves were not acorporeal in the way that Wright seems to imply), they would be truly somatic (bodily). However, that is far less of a change than he wishes it were.

The important emphasis is that a future life that had something to do with a change in philosophy was generally valued. The point, though, is that the worldviews he expresses does not find it important. Take, for example, what he says about Seneca and the general apathy toward future life everlasting:
For Seneca, the immortal human soul has come from beyond this world – from among the stars, in fact – and will make its way back there. Though one might hold that it simply disappeared, it is more likely that it will go to be with the gods. Death is either the end of everything, in which case there is nothing to be alarmed about, or it is a process of change, in which case, since the change is bound to be for the better, one should be glad.[5]
Seneca – like many stoics – was simply indifferent to the issue of death. There might well be something in the future, there might well not; however, that was not the goal of human life.

The worldview of Greco-Roman society was far less one of disdain toward any discussion of resurrection; rather, it was general indifference. The vast majority of people would not have heard the message of a physical resurrection as troubling because they felt any future life should not be physical – they would have been indifferent to the calling of the question in the first place. This is the emphasis that would have been more rich for Wright to explore.

There were minorities, however, who did think of life after death as something to be taken very seriously. These are most easily found in the mystery cults and in Greek magic. These groups did very much focus upon a future life in which ethics often determined one’s future (the latter being more true of mystery cults than magic). Wright does briefly bring up mystery cults arguing that they held the same goal as Platonists with less work:
Already in Socrates’ time the mystery religions had begun to flourish, offering (so it seemed) a comparable benefit to philosophical wisdom but without the hard intellectual work. Beginning with the Orphic cult, but fanning out much more widely, these religions (if that is indeed the right term for them) offered the initiate access to a world of private spiritual experience in the present time which would continue into the world beyond death.[6]
He argues that the eventual goal of the mystery cults was not a bodily resurrection and therefore can simply be folded inside Platonism. The problem, though, is the issue of indifference cited above. Many Platonists would be generally indifferent about a future life – they expected it, but it was not their main concern. By contrast, a reasonable argument can be made that the mystery cults were very much interested in an afterlife and it was their main concern. Therefore, real question arises as to why Wright does not discuss this issue further. He does bring up mystery cults one more time, but the conversation is so clipped that it is hard to follow:
These multifarious and sophisticated cults enacted the god’s death and resurrection as a metaphor, whose concrete referent was the cycle of seed-time and harvest, of human reproduction and fertility. Sometimes as in Egypt, these myths and rituals include funerary practices: the aspiration of the dead was to become united with Osiris. But the new life they might thereby experience was not a return to the life of the present world. Nobody actually expected the mummies to get up, walk about and resume normal living; nobody in that world would have wanted such a thing, either. That which Homer and others meant by resurrection was not affirmed by the devotees of Osiris or their cousins elsewhere.[7]
Why would this be different? Why is this not an important element to delve into very deeply? Wright does not clearly explain.

This omission is further exacerbated for Wright’s eventual goal – to see how the message of Jesus and his resurrection would have sounded to a gentile audience. The one thing Christianity might have sounded like would be a mystery cult. Therefore, to simply ignore major elements of them and instead to focus on Homer does not make a tremendous amount of sense – except in the most vague terms as a general “worldview” – magic and mystery cults were minority religions – but they did exist. It seems that his narrow discussion of resurrection from the dead has eliminated conversation that well should have occurred.

In all, his conversation of the general worldview is strong; however, his details could have been far more carefully managed to create a more robust picture.


[1] RSG, 33.
[2] RSG, 82.
[3] RSG, 43-44.
[4] RSG, 48.
[5] RSG, 54.
[6] RSG, 51.
[7] RSG, 80-81.

No comments:

Post a Comment